Bare Essentials

This post is merely a skeletal companion piece to the more fleshed-out summary of Cyrenaic practice found here. It consists only of the essential points to keep in mind as we navigate the world, without excess information.

Bare Essentials:

Our immediate, subjective, sensory affections vouch for themselves, not whatever they appear to represent, and they do so inwardly, unmistakably, truly and incorrigibly. They are our only source of knowledge. The passage and dissolution of fleeting sensations and images is where analysis leaves off.  

Pleasure is self-evidently choice-worthy, pain is self-evidently avoidance-worthy, and no other experiences possess these monadic axiological characteristics. Our ethical project is a life organized around the life-guiding truth of pleasure and pain — the only natural, native, and concrete referents for our understanding of good and evil. 

The highest good is one’s own pleasure, and the end is to live pleasantly, which is happiness. All other goods are instrumental to securing one’s own pleasure. The pursuit of pleasures is balanced with the value of maintaining freedom from mental distress and from bodily pain. Perception of the world is made in terms of opportunities for enjoyment and risks of suffering, informing our hedonic calculus in the economy of pleasure.

The pleasures of the present experience are to be enjoyed fully as our highest goal, without undue concern for what has passed or what is to come, which is self-defeating. Pleasant living is to be accomplished within each individual unit of time, enjoying what is at hand, without excessive toil or yearning for what is not currently available. 

We skilfully cultivate an earthen character, with virile consciousness of the natural and instinctive sentiments of the body and the affections our flesh defines — a poetic apprehension of experience united with something of personal ambition and self-assertion. This opens an aesthetic dimension of pleasure-seeking. We regard all objects — works of art, the fairer forms of nature and human life, engaging personalities — as powers or forces producing pleasurable sensations, each of a more or less peculiar, unique kind. 

We adorn and beautify, in scrupulous self-respect, our souls, and whatever our souls touch upon — these bodies, the raiments we wear, our pastimes, and the intercourse of society. We build ourselves in accordance with a beatific vision of successful living — exemplified by heroic, impassioned, and joyful modes of being and behaving, taken from living or artistically depicted examples. To burn always with this hard, gem-like flame, to maintain this ecstasy, is success in life. 

To strong sensual passions we must unite a calm regulative intellect, in order to indulge various pleasures without being worsted. We temper our enjoyment with moderation, holding dominion over desires by keeping in mind what really matters and what does not. What really matters is simply to avoid pain and distress, and to experience some sort of pleasure. We achieve the former by disdaining excess. This does not entail embracing austerity, because excess is relative to what is actually good — pleasure. We do not exclude luxury, if available, but avoid becoming attached or dependent on specific sources of pleasure, and reduce our desires accordingly. Temperance also enables enjoyment: those with a sound mind can indulge freely in luxurious pleasures without becoming corrupted — that is, beginning to feel these are necessities.

We keep an easy and yielding disposition, with infinite mirth, adapting ourselves to place, time, and role, performing harmoniously in any circumstance. With confidence, healthy virtue, and elegant vice, we feel comfortable rather than anxious or fearful in unknown or threatening situations. Paradoxically, it is only a person of firm character and profound insight who can be so malleable, adapting comfortably to every situation.

Our easy gaiety and careless enjoyment aids sociability, and we are capable of getting along with any sort of person whatsoever, and can do so without anxiety. This social confidence is based on the understanding both cognitively and emotionally that all we need is to avoid pain and discover some modicum of pleasure, so we feel more relaxed around other people. We do not need to impress anyone, since we are not after anything another can provide which we could not procure for ourselves. Just about every situation presents opportunities for enjoyment, which encourages simple accommodation of ourselves to our company at any given moment.

Suavity involves training responsiveness, versatility, and adroitness. The wise man is comfortable in any situation, and adroit enough to turn it to his advantage. He speaks well, with knowledge and sophistication, possessing charm, humor, and quick-wittedness.


Pleasure Principles

The following program is a result of my own philosophical reflection upon, and distillation of, Ancient Cyrenaic material, augmented by the later aesthetic developments and creative reinterpretations of Walter Pater. My personal approach to philosophy proceeds ever with an eye towards practical application. The theory or idea which does not inform somehow one’s attitude and actions is idle — of no consequence. As a result, this summary is not presented as rigorous theory, but as a pragmatic code informing outlook and behavior. I have cannibalized content from prior writing in order to create this current pastiche, and am liable to update its content as my understanding evolves. As always, all credit for originality properly belongs to past figures, from whose efforts I pilfer.

Pleasure Principles:

Maintain complete fidelity to the subjective experience of immediate sensory impressions as the sole origin and criteria of knowledge. These affections vouch for themselves, and they do so inwardly, unmistakably, truly, and incorrigibly. Accordingly, we have inferior epistemic access to other alleged sources for guidance of action and care. This focus induces a drily practical purgative skepticism, justifying withdrawal of interest, and suspension of judgement, regarding speculative metaphysical theorizing about what may lie beyond or behind experiential phenomena. With the individual for our standard, we are unable to wholly accept the valuations of others without personal verification, foundational for intellectual integrity. 

Only the feelings of pleasure and pain possess monadic qualities of attraction and repulsion, respectively. Pleasure is self-evidently choice-worthy, pain is self-evidently avoidance-worthy, and no other experiences possess these monadic qualities. We organize our lives around the life-guiding truth of pleasure and pain. The highest good is my own pleasure, and the end is to live pleasantly. All other goods are of instrumental value. The maximal achievement, appreciation, and enjoyment of pleasurable experiences across a lifetime constitutes happiness. The pursuit of pleasure is balanced with maintaining freedom from mental distress and bodily pain. Perception of the world is made in terms of opportunities for enjoyment, and risks of suffering, informing our hedonic calculus in the economy of pleasure.

The feeling of pleasure, like all affections, occurs only while it is being experienced — it is unitemporal. The present alone is truly real, and we yield completely to its improvement. We telescope our focus of concern and care to the present moment as a spiritual exercise, prudential rule of thumb, and emotional attitude — not an ontological straight-jacket. We exclude all embarrassment alike of regret for the past and calculation for the future, as far as possible, and train ourselves to focus on what is before us, not what is absent. We thereby diminish discomfort and become more receptive to present pleasures. Pleasant living is to be accomplished within each individual unit of time. Due to the greater ability to affect the present moment, we put less faith in painstaking long-term planning than in our ability to adapt to circumstances.

Education shapes our character by training tranquility, social mastery, and connoisseurshipIn order to achieve happiness, we must transform our behavior and attitude so we can rationally secure, maintain, and enjoy pleasurable experiences, while minimising negative consequences. This involves transforming slavish characters into free ones by cultivating self-possession/-mastery, the capacity to speak with sophistication, and proper philosophical understanding. Education thereby removes impediments to the purest and most immediate reception of pleasurable experiences, including anxiety, regret, and unjustified (merely conventional) compunctions. Training also includes cultivation of appetite and the refinement of its satisfaction, increasing capacity for appreciation. We skilfully cultivate an earthen character, with virile consciousness of the sentiments of the body and the affections our flesh defines — a poetic apprehension of experience united with something of personal ambition and self-assertion. This opens an aesthetic dimension of pleasure-seeking. We regard all objects, works of art, the fairer forms of nature and human life, engaging personalities, as powers or forces producing pleasurable sensations, each of a more or less peculiar or unique kind. 

To indulge in various pleasures without being worsted, we must exercise self-control and train certain excellencies. Temperance involves disdaining excess desires and curbing dependency on any particular allures, as the sentimental and practical application of the precept of true value. What really matters is simply to avoid pain and distress, and to experience some sort of pleasure. Excess is relative to what is actually good: pleasure. This does not exclude luxury, but we avoid becoming attached to specific sources of pleasure and reduce our desires accordingly. Practical reason involves applying the rational account of what is good and what is bad to particular situations, and choosing correctly — this also provides a sound foundation for rhetoric. Adaptability signifies that we possess the ability to harmonize with place, time, and role, and perform harmoniously in any circumstance. Paradoxically, it is only a person of firm character and profound insight who can be so malleable, adapting comfortably to every situation. Confidence means feeling comfortable rather than anxious or fearful in unknown or threatening situations. Sociability denotes the ability to get along with any sort of person whatsoever, and to do so without anxiety. This social confidence is based on the understanding both cognitively and emotionally that all we need is to avoid pain and discover some modicum of pleasure. We not need to impress anyone, since we are not after anything they can provide which we could not procure for ourselves. Just about every situation presents opportunities for enjoyment, which encourages simple accommodation of oneself to one’s company and situation at any given moment. Suavity involves training responsiveness, versatility, and adroitness. The wise man is comfortable in any situation, and adroit enough to turn it to his advantage. He speaks well, with knowledge and sophistication, possessing charm, humor, and quick-wittedness.

Friendships, familial relationships, and romantic partnerships are entered into or continued for self-interested motives due to the pleasures they command. Natural affection follows and we become pleased seeing those we care about happy, motivating us to help ensure their well-being. Magnanimity and concern are important interpersonal qualities. Justice is the prudent course of action because of the pleasant social consequences which follow. This means being generally fair, meritorious, and law-abiding in our dealings with others. We have an empathetic distaste for causing or witnessing pain and discomfort. We appeal to the aesthetic revulsion caused by the ugliness of suffering, prompting an amelioration of its causes if reasonable, and an avoidance of behavior which would bring it about. Veneration for life itself is due to our immediate grasp of the inherently distressing nature of pain and suffering.

Walter Pater’s Philosophy: A Snapshot

In an earlier post I briefly outlined the orthodox Cyrenaic philosophical scheme, drawn primarily from the example of Aristippus himself in regards to ethical and sentimental content, supported by the epistemological developments contributed primarily by his grandson, the Metrodidact. Though not entirely rigorous in terms of historical accuracy (we have a pastiche outlining the basic commitments of the school, drawn from various anecdotes and doxographies, often hostile), nevertheless, I believe it is entirely within the pragmatic spirit of early Cyrenaicism and represents the school’s primary concerns and considerations. I find it valuable to reference a broad outline, focusing on the practical implications of each philosophical point, in order to better orient ourselves and structure our pursuits. After all, what’s of utmost importance is making our individual lives pleasant, not constructing an exhaustive ideology. Such an attitude of indifference to speculative constructs is a more authentic reflection of early Cyrenaicism than blind submission to an abstract theory. To the degree the ancient Cyrenaics involve themselves in eristics, they are entirely guided by affective commitments, and once satisfied of having reached greater consistency, or fended off some plausible criticism, they cease elaborating. 

With this in mind, I’d like to attempt a similar exposition of Walter Pater’s New Cyrenaicism, briefly organising its additional dimensions with reference to the underlying structure of the orthodox view. As a refined modern aesthete, Pater inventively commandeers the philosophical material of his spiritual predecessors and renovates the existing elements to suit his tastes. These updates have much to recommend them for a sympathetic contemporary reader. An important consideration rests with the pre-existing sensibilities of the would-be Cyrenaic. It’s worth asking yourself, before weighing the content, if your concerns are our concerns, your values our values. Otherwise, you may find more appeal in competing schools, (may I recommend Epicureanism as an outstanding alternative?) and if our brethren provide you with the fulfilment and happiness you are seeking, all the better. 

Something interesting to note is that, as the novel illustrating the development of New Cyrenaicism progresses, the protagonist comes to adopt, not merely the “first lesson” of Heraclitus - the metaphysical grounding in constant renewal for his scrupulous commitment to immediate experience - but also embraces something of his pantheistic organizing principle, the logos. I will have more to say regarding the intersection of Heraclitean metaphysics with Cyrenaic epistemology at a later date, but, a word of caution: while our tacit skepticism regarding ontological commitments does not prohibit sweeping generalizations from engulfing experiential phenomena, which includes the observation of causal regularity, we should properly subordinate this conceptual investigation to its appropriate position — that is, facilitating the pleasurable appreciation of some aspect of our waking world, which may otherwise remain neglected. I therefore pull short here of describing Marius’ concession to the notion of a universal “unfailing companion” amid his contact with early Christianity. This development, though fascinating, represents a divergence away from our core concerns as Cyrenaics. To interested readers, I recommend the second volume of Marius: The Epicurean

I now present Walter Pater’s New Cyrenaicism:

Epistemology:

  • Purgative Skepticism: Acquiesence to the Heraclitean flux of impressions justifies withdrawal of interest from universal “objective” knowledge, beyond that which can be accessed through sense-perception, eliminating concerns with vast speculative metaphysics and intrinsic axiological imperatives. Consequently, this drily practical skepticism induces an anti-metaphysical metaphysic, disabused of the ambition to pass beyond “the flaming ramparts of the world”
  • Empiricist Idealism: Complete fidelity to immediate experience — direct sensation — as the only criteria of truth. Constructing the world in great measure from within, by exercising meditative powers of selective focus upon our impressions, according to a vein of subjectivist philosophy with the individual for its standard, we are unable to wholly accept the valuations of others without personal verification. The object, the experience, as it will be known to memory, is really from first to last the chief point of consideration in the conduct of life.
  • Presentism: The present moment alone is truly real, and we yield to its improvement, excluding all embarrassment alike of regret for the past and calculation for the future, as far as possible. The result of our purgative skepticism is the acknowledgement that what is secure in our existence is but the sharp apex of the present moment between two hypothetical eternities, and all that is real in our experience but a series of fleeting impression.
  • Intellectual Integrity: Insight, free from ghostly idols, sends us back to experience, to the world of concrete impressions, with a liberated soul. With sober discretion of one’s thoughts, a sustained habit of meditation, the sense of the negative conclusions reached above enables us to concentrate ourselves upon what is immediately here and now, providing a peculiar manner of intellectual confidence as we live intently in the visible world.
Ethics:
  • Aesthetic-Moral Idealism: Projecting and living a vision of the successful life. We adorn and beautify, in scrupulous self-respect, our souls, and whatever our souls touch upon — these wonderful bodies, these material dwelling-places through which the shadows pass together for a while, the very raiments we wear, our very pastimes and the intercourse of society. In other words, we learn and practice character, health, style, and sociability. True aesthetic culture is realizable as a new form of the contemplative life, founded on the vision of perfect men and things. Whatever form of human life which may be heroic, impassioned, ideal: these are the criterion of values. Skilled cultivation of life, of experience, of opportunity. Dilligent promotion of the capacity of the eye, to be “made perfect by the love of visible beauty”. The soul, which can make no sincere claim to have apprehended anything beyond the veil of immediate experience, yet never loses a sense of happiness in conforming to the highest moral ideal it can clearly define for itself. 
  • Unitemporal Pleasure: Imperative to enliven each passing moment, in order to enter the “ideal now”. Much of the pleasant life is lived, also, in reminiscence, and it is proper to the economy of conduct to ask what value current action will hold upon reflection, once it has passed. Boundless appetite for experience, for adventure, whether physical or of the spirit. Follow the percept: Be perfect in regard to what is here and now; the precept of “culture”, as it is called, or of a complete education. To us, at least, in whom the fleeting impressions — faces, voices, material sunshine — are very real and imperious, we might well set ourselves to the consideration, how such actual moments as they pass might be made to yield their utmost, by the most dexterous training of capacity. Arresting the desirable moments as they pass, and prolonging their life a little. — To live in the concrete. To be sure, at least, of one’s hold upon that. This philosophic scheme is but the reflection of the data of sense, and chiefly of sight.
  • Health: Vivid sense of the value of mental and bodily sanity; recognition of the beauty, even for the aesthetic sense, of mere bodily health. Honor the restorative benefits of sleep.
  • Adaptability: We maintain harmony with the change and motion inherent in existence by constantly renewed mobility of character.
  • Hedonic Economy: The deeper wisdom has ever been, with a sense of economy, with a jealous estimate of gain and loss, to use life, not as the means to some problematic end, but as an end in itself.
  • Education and Refinement: Training sensitivity to aesthetic delights, judged based on the virtuous merits regarding their degree, type, and unique sensory impressions with which they affect the individual’s “imaginative reason”. We refine all instruments of inward and outward intuition and impression, developing our capacities, in order to best receive and interact with the “beatific vision” of our experience in the world. This training involves, not the conveyance of doctrine or principles, but rather, the teaching of an art. Education increases one’s capacity for enjoyment 
  • Temperance: As a means to keeping the eye clean by a sort of exquisite personal alacrity and cleanliness; to meditate upon beautiful visible objects; to avoid jealously everything repugnant to sight. How little any of us really need, when people leave us alone, with the intellectual powers at work serenely. The drops of falling water, a few wild flowers with their priceless fragrance, a few tufts even of half-dead leaves, changing colour in the quiet of a room that has but light and shadow in it; these, for a susceptible mind, might well do duty for all the glory of Augustus.
  • Earthen Character: Development generally of the more human and earthly elements of character. Virile consciousness of the realities of life, poetic apprehension, united with something of personal ambition and self-assertion. The earthly end comes like a final revelation of nothing less than the soul’s extinction. To the sentiment of the body, and the affections it defined — the flesh — one must cling; a materialist with the temper of a devotee. Amid abstract metaphysical doubts, as to what might lie one step only beyond that experience, we reinforce the deep original materialism or eathliness of human nature itself, bound so intimately to the sensuous world — let us at least make the most of what is “here and now”. 

Relationships:

  • Sympathy: Empathetic distaste for causing or witnessing pain/discomfort. An appeal to the aesthetic revulsion caused by the ugliness of suffering, prompting an amelioration of its causes, and an avoidance of behavior which would bring it about. Sympathy for all creatures, something of a religious veneration for life itself.  How tenderly—more tenderly than many stricter souls—we might yield to kindly instinct, what fineness of charity in passing judgment on others, what an exquisite conscience of other men’s susceptibilities. We go beyond most people in our care for all weakly creatures; judging, instinctively, that to be but sentient is to possess rights. Are those sufferings, great or little, of more real consequence to others than mine to me?
  • Companionship: The pleasant value of association with others. Companionship, indeed, familiarity with others, gifted in this way or that, or at least pleasant, are through one or another long span of life, the chief delight of the journey.
Sources:

Lampe, K. (2017). The Birth of Hedonism - The Cyrenaic Philosophers and Pleasure As a Way of Life. Princeton University Press.

Pater, W. (1893). Plato and Platonism. Praeger.

Pater, W. (1973). Marius the Epicurean. Blackwell.

Pater, W. (2019). The Renaissance: Studies in Art and Poetry. Litres.

“Sources and Testimonies” from The Epistemology of the Cyrenaic School by Voula Tsouna

Below is a selection of Voula Tsouna’s The Epistemology of the Cyrenaic School, taken from the appendix of this work, which collects together important historical sources and testimonies. I have reproduced and lightly edited this content here for ease of reference. Interested readers are encouraged to investigate Tsouna’s excellent work directly in order to benefit from her analysis of ancient Cyrenaic epistemology.

Sources and Testimonies:

The evidence on Cyrenaic epistemology comes from secondary sources and consists entirely of testimonies, not of fragments. None of the titles mentioned in the lists of the doxographers seems to be of an epistemological treatise. But the lists refer only to the works of Aristippus of Cyrene, Theodorus and Hegesias, and none of them is known to have had detailed epistemological views. The epistemology of the school may have been developed in treatises of Aristippus the Younger and Anniceris, probably under the heading of ethics.

Although the testimonies are second-hand and occur principally in polemical contexts, they are often based on good sources and constitute reliable evidence about the Cyrenaic positions. Also, the polemical arguments brought against these positions by ancient authors are fre- quently enlightening. In my selection of texts, I have included the epistemological testimonies, and also materials on psychology and ethics that have a bearing on the topics that I discuss.

1. Colotes and Plutarch:

Our earliest source on the Cyrenaic theory of knowledge is Colotes, a young contemporary of Epicurus. After Epicurus’ death (270 BC) and Arcesilaus’ ascent to the leadership of the Academy (c. 261 BC) Colotes wrote a book entitled On the Fact that it is not Possible even to Live according to the Doctrines of the Other Philosophers, in which he criticised the doctrines of Parmenides, Empedocles, Socrates, Melissus, Plato, Stilpo, and two schools which he does not name but which are easily identified as the Cyrenaics and the followers of Arcesilaus. His main aim was to prove that doctrines directly or indirectly undermining the credibility of the senses make life impossible. It is in this context that Colotes attempted to describe and ridicule the Cyrenaic theory of knowledge.

The evidence about Colotes’ attack against the Cyrenaics comes from the first–second century AD writer Plutarch. In his work Against Colotes, Plutarch cited Colotes’ criticisms, stated that they were grounded on a historically inaccurate rendering of the Cyrenaic doctrine, and gave what he claimed to be the true letter of this doctrine. Subsequently, he argued that the Cyrenaics and the Epicureans in fact held the same views concerning the truth of sense-impressions and that, therefore, by criticising the Cyrenaics Colotes contradicts himself. Thus, the passage from Plutarch’s work contains two pieces of evidence about the epistemology of the Cyrenaics, which are both chronologically and philosophically distinct: a third-century BC version of the doctrine offered by an Epicurean writer of the same period and a first-century AD version given and commented upon by Plutarch.

Plutarch, Against Colotes:

At any rate, after dealing with the philosophers of the past, [c] Colotes turns to the philosophers of his own time without mentioning the name of any of them; yet, the proper thing for him to do would have been to refute them too by naming them, or not to name the philosophers of the past either. And he, who so often criticised Socrates and Plato and Parmenides with his pen, obviously lost his nerve when he was to deal with the living philosophers; he was not moderate in his criticisms because he was respectful, or he would have shown respect to their betters (sc. the philosophers of the past). I guess he intends to refute the Cyrenaics in the first place and the Academy of Arcesilaus in the second place. The latter were the philosophers who suspended judgement about everything; but the former, placing all pathe! and all sense-impressions within themselves, [d] believed that the evidence coming from them is not sufficient regarding assertions about external objects. Instead, distancing them- selves from external objects, they shut themselves up within their pathē as in a state of siege, using the formula ‘it appears’ but refusing to affirm in addition that ‘it is’ with regard to external objects.

This is why, says Colotes, the Cyrenaics can neither live nor cope with things. In addition, he says, making fun of them, that ‘these men do not say that a man or a horse or a wall is, but that they themselves are being walled or horsed or manned’. In the first place, he is using these expressions maliciously, just as a professional denouncer would. Doubtless, these consequences amongst others do follow from the teachings of these men. Yet he should have presented the doctrine in the form in which those philosophers teach it. [e] They say we are being sweetened and bittered and chilled and warmed and illuminated and darkened, each of these pathe! having within itself its own evidence, which is intrinsic to it and irreversible. But whether the honey is sweet or the young olive-shoot bitter or the hail chilly or the unmixed wine warm or the sun luminous or the night air dark, is contested by many witnesses, [wild] animals and domesticated animals and humans alike, for some dislike honey, others like olive-shoots or are burned off by hail or are chilled by the wine or go blind in the sunlight and see well at night.[f] So, when opinion stays close to the pathē it preserves its infallibility, but when it oversteps them and meddles with judgements and assertions about external objects, it often both disturbs itself and fights against other people who receive from the same objects contrary pathē and different sense-impressions.

It would seem that Colotes has the same trouble as boys who are just starting to learn how to read. While they are used to spelling the characters on their tablets, when they see these characters written on others things outside the tablets, they are doubtful and confused. And so with him: the views which he follows eagerly and treats with respect when they occur in the writings of Epicurus, he neither understands nor identifies when they are asserted by others. Those who maintain that when a film of atoms rounded at the corners, or again another one which is bent, comes into contact with our senses, the sensation is truly imprinted, but who do not allow us to affirm as well that the tower is round or the oar is bent, do establish as true their own pathē and sense-appearances but do not want to concede that the external objects have these characteristics. And just as those philosophers (sc. the Cyrenaics) are committed to speaking about being horsed or being walled but not about a horse or a wall, so these philosophers (sc. the Epicureans) must say that the eye is rounded or with rough angles [b] and not that the oar is bent or the tower round. The film of atoms from which the eye has been affected is bent, whereas the oar from which the film of atoms has come is not bent. Thus, since the pathos differs from the object, it is necessary for belief either to stick to the pathos or to be refuted whenever it asserts how things are in addition to how things appear. As to the fact that they protest aloud and are vexed on behalf of sensation, which is to say that they do not affirm that the external object is warm but only that the pathos inherent in sensation is warm, is that statement not the same as the [Cyrenaic] statement about taste, i.e. that they (sc. the Cyrenaics) do not say that the external object is sweet, but that a pathos or a movement of this kind related to taste has occurred? [c] But the person who says that he is receiving a man-like sense-impression but is not sensing whether there is a man, from where has he got his original idea? Was it not from the philosophers who claim that they receive a curve-like sense-impression but that the sight does not go further to affirm that something is curved or round, but a sense-appearance or imprint of round form related to sight has occurred?

‘Most certainly,’ one will answer. ‘But for my part, after I come close to the tower and after I touch the oar, I shall assert that the oar is straight and that the tower is angular; but this other person, even if he gets close he will admit what seems to be the case and what appears to him, but nothing more.’ [d] Indeed, my dear friend, he will not, since he is better than you in observing and defending the logical consequences of his doctrine, that all sense-impressions alike are trustworthy about themselves and no sense-impression is trustworthy about anything else but all are equally good witnesses. And here is the end of your doctrine that all sense-impressions are true and none is unreliable or false, if indeed you think that this category of sense-impressions must state additional truths about the external objects, whereas you refused to trust that other category of sense-impressions in anything beyond the pathos itself. If they have an equal claim to trustworthiness, whether they occur as the result of observing an object closely or at a distance, it is only fair either to confer on all sense-impressions the power of making additional judgements about how things are, or to subtract that power from the former category of sense-impressions as well as from the latter. But if there is a difference in the pathos affecting one when one is at a distance and when one is close at hand, it is false to assert that no sense-impression and no sensation [e] is more evident than another. Likewise, what they call attestation and contestation have nothing to do with sensation but rather with belief. Thus, if they urge us to make assertions about the external objects by following these, they transfer the object of judgement from what is unfailingly true to what is often wrong. But why do we need to talk at present about views which are full of confusion and which contradict themselves?

2. Philodemus (?):

Approximately two centuries after Colotes and one century before Plutarch, the Cyrenaic doctrine may be briefly mentioned in an anonymous incomplete text on Epicurean ethics, probably composed in the first half of the first century BC by the Epicurean philosopher Philodemus of Gadara. The text was found in a Herculaneum papyrus, commonly known as ‘the Comparetti Ethics’ after the name of its first editor. The Cyrenaics are not named in it and their identification is conjectural. The evidence that appears to concern them occurs in the second and third columns of the papyrus, both of which are badly damaged. Their context is uncertain. But it is probable that in the first three columns of the text, the Epicurean author launched an attack against anti-rationalism, especially against positions undermining the belief that moral choices are performed according to rational calculation and on the basis of factual knowledge. His claim is, I think, that the epistemological views of the Cyrenaics dictated a kind of hedonism which precluded rational choice and rational justification of one’s actions. This text merits attention, since it is the only evidence that may refer explicitly to the philosophical relation between the epistemology and the ethics of the Cyrenaic school.

PHerc. 0250 [Philodemus] [On Choices and Avoidances]

Col. II . . . and they claim that in truth no (judgement) takes precedence over any other, being persuaded that the great pathos of the soul occurs as a result of pain and that thus we accomplish our choices and avoidances by observing both (sc. bodily and mental pain). It is not possible that the joys arise in us in the same way and all together, in accordance with some expectation . . .

Col. III . . . and some people denied that it is possible to know anything. And, further, they added that if nothing is present on account of which one should make an immediate choice, then one should not choose immediately. Some other people, having selected the pathē of the soul as the moral ends and as not in need of additional judgement based on further criteria, granted to everybody an authority, which was not accountable, to take pleasure in whatever they cared to name and to do whatever contributed to it. And yet others held the doctrine that what our school calls grief or joy are totally empty notions because of the manifest indeterminacy of things . . .

3. The Anonymous Theaetatus Commentator:

Another Greek source is the commentary on Plato’s Theaetetus, the only ancient commentary on that dialogue to survive to our days (Berlin papyrus 9782). Its author remains anonymous. He is probably a Middle Platonist, and his floruit may be anywhere between the first century BC and the second century AD. The seventy-five columns of the papyrus cover a relatively short part of the dialogue, from its opening at 042a to the application of the theory of perpetual flux to sense-perception at 053d. The epistemological position of the Cyrenaics is mentioned in connection with Theaetetus’ attempt to answer the question what is knowledge by defining knowledge as sense-perception.

The anonymous author comments on the Protagorean thesis that as things appear to one, so they are for one, and on the Heraclitean doctrine of flux brought in support of the epistemological relativism of Protagoras: in a universe of perpetual flux, nothing has a stable identity, for neither the perceiving subject or faculty nor the perceived object exist in themselves, but only in so far as they are perceived; so, things are for me such as they affect me and they are for you such as they affect you and, according to this hypothesis, man is the judge and measure of the affections or conditions which he experiences. Subsequently, the author attempts to clarify the application of the theory to the case of the perception of the wind by different people. He stresses that, according to the Protagorean–Heraclitean theory, different perceivers are affected differently by the same wind, in the same place, at the same time. The proponents of the theory conclude that the wind causing these pathe! is neither cold nor not cold, but that in reality it does not have such properties; for if a thing does have an intrinsic property, then it cannot produce different pathe! in different perceivers in the same conditions and at the same time. The author’s suggestion is that the Cyrenaic position, that only the pathē are apprehensible but the external objects are inapprehensible, is based on comparable grounds: we cannot tell whether the fire has the property of burning, because if it did, then all things that came into contact with it would be affected in the same way, i.e. they would burn.

The surviving commentary on the Theaetetus does not cover the part of the dialogue which contains the theory of the ‘subtler’ philosophers. However, the claim of its author that there is a close philosophical relation between the Protagorean–Heraclitean doctrine in Plato’s Theaetetus and the epistemological views of the Cyrenaics prefigures modern interpretations tending to identify these two doctrines.

Anonymous commentator on Plato’s Theaetetus:

Whence the Cyrenaics claim that the pathē alone are apprehensible but the external objects inapprehensible, for, they say, I apprehend that I am being burnt, but it is non-evident whether the fire is such as to burn. If it were such, all things would be burnt by it.

 4. Cicero:

The earliest and most important Latin author reporting physiological and psychological views of the Cyrenaics is Cicero, the Roman politician and intellectual of the first century BC, whose philosophical viewpoint is shaped by Academic scepticism. In his work Lucullus, three passages offer important evidence about the Cyrenaic doctrine: an argument defending the power of the senses to comprehend their peculiar objects, which mentions the so-called internal touch – the sensory channel through which, according to the Cyrenaics, we apprehend the pathē; an argument destined to undermine belief in the credibility of the senses, which contains, again, a brief reference to the Cyrenaic position that the only things which can be apprehended are those experienced by internal touch; and a set of remarks aiming to locate the position of Antiochus on the subject of the criterion of truth, where the criteria of Protagoras, the Cyrenaics and the Epicureans are grouped together in opposition to Plato’s rationalistic criterion.

4a. Cicero, Lucullus 08-22:

08. . . .Thus, the whole discourse against the Academy is undertaken by us in this manner, so that we preserve the definition which Philo wanted to subvert; unless we make it prevail, we concede that nothing can be perceived.

09. So, let us start from the senses, whose judgements are so clear and certain that if our nature were given the choice and were asked by some god whether she was satisfied with her senses when they are intact and uninjured or whether she asked for something better, I cannot see what more she could require. Nor indeed do I have to delay here while I respond to the examples of the bent oar or the pigeon’s neck since I am not the one to say that whatever object is seen is such as it appears. Epicurus may reflect upon that and upon many other things. But, according to my judgement, the greatest truth lies in the senses, if they are healthy and powerful and if all obstacles and impediments are removed. This is why we often want to change the light and the position of the things which we are observing, and we either diminish or increase the distance between them and us, and we do many things until sheer sight acquires confidence in its own judgement. The same happens with sounds, smell or taste, so that there is none of us who wishes for a finer judgement in the senses, each in its own kind.

21. Indeed, when practice and skill are added in order for the eyes to comprehend a painting and the ears music, who is there who will not perceive how much power lies in the senses? How many things painters may see in shadows and in the light parts of the painting which we do not see! How many things which escape us in music are listened to by those trained in this kind of thing, who as soon as the flute-player blows the first note affirm that this is Antiope or Andromache, while we do not even suspect it! There is no need to talk at all about taste and smell, in which there is a certain power of apprehension, albeit defective. Why should we speak of touch and indeed of what the philosophers call internal touch of either pleasure or pain, in which alone, the Cyrenaics believe, lies the criterion of the true because it (sc. the true) is sensed [through it]? So, can anybody say that there is no difference between the man who is in pain and the man who experiences pleasure, or is it that the person who thinks so is clearly insane?

20. But then, the things which we claim to be perceived by the senses are of the same kind as those which are said to be perceived not by the senses themselves but in some way through the senses, as for instance: ‘This is white’, ‘This is sweet’, ‘This is harmonious’, ‘This is fragrant’, ‘This is rough.’ Surely, these we believe to be grasped by the mind, not by the senses. Thus, ‘This is a horse’, ‘This is a dog’. Then follows the rest of the series connecting more complexconcepts,forinstancethosewhichincludeasitwereacomplete understanding of things: ‘If one is a man, one is a rational mortal animal.’ From this latter kind are imprinted upon us our primary notions of things, without which all understanding and enquiry and discussion are impossible.

22. Now, if there were false primary notions (for you seemed to render ennoiai by ‘notions’) – if, then, these were false or imprinted by appearances of such a kind that could not be distinguished from false ones, how would we make use of them after all? And how could we see what is consistent with any given thing and what is inconsistent with it? At any rate, no room at all is left for memory, which more than anything else sustains not only philosophy but also all practice of life and all the arts. How can there possibly be a memory of what is false? Or what can anyone remember that one does not understand and hold in one’s mind? Indeed, what art can there be that does not consist, not of one or two, but of many mental percepts? And if you do away with it, how will you distinguish the expert from the ignorant? We shall not claim at random that this man is an expert and the other is not, unless we see the one remember what he has perceived and understood while the other does not. And just as one category of arts is such as to discern things only with the mind, and another such as to do or to construct something, how can the geometrician discern things that are either non-existent or cannot be distinguished from false ones, or how can the player of the harp perfect his rhythms and complete his verses? The same result will also occur in other arts of this kind, whose entire performance consists in making and doing; for what can be accomplished by an art unless the man who will exercise it has learned many mental percepts?

4b. Cicero, Lucullus 75-6:

75. Do I not give you the impression that I do not simply mention the names of illustrious men, as Saturninus did, but also I always take as my model someone who is famous and noble? And yet, I could mention philosophers who are troublesome to your school but of small importance – Stilpo, Diodorus, Alexinus, the authors of certain intricate and cunning sophismata (for this is how deceitful and trifling riddles are called). But why should I bring them in, when I have Chrysippus who is supposed to sustain the portico of the Stoics? How many arguments he produced against the senses and against everything that is approved in ordinary usage! But, you will retort, he also refuted them. In fact he does not seem to me to have done so. But suppose that he did: yet, surely, he would not have gathered so many arguments which might deceive us because of their great probability, had he not seen that they could not easily be resisted.

76. What do you think of the Cyrenaics, by no means contemptible philosophers? They deny that there is anything that can be perceived from the outside: the only things that they do perceive are those which they sense by internal touch, for instance pain or pleasure, and they do not know whether something has a particular colour or sound, but only sense that they are themselves affected in a certain way.

4c. Cicero, Lucullus 042-3:

042. I come now to the third part of philosophy. One criterion is that of Protagoras, who holds that what appears to a person is true for that person, another is that of the Cyrenaics, who believe that there is no criterion whatso- ever except the inmost affects, another is that of Epicurus, who places the whole criterion in the senses and in the primary notions of things and in pleasure. On the other hand, Plato believed that the whole criterion of truth and truth itself lies merely in reasoning and in the mind, detached from belief and from the senses.

043. Surely our friend Antiochus does not endorse any of this?

5. Aristocles:

Another Greek source is Aristocles of Messene, a second-century AD Peripatetic philosopher whose work is partly preserved by Eusebius of Caesarea in his Preparation for the Gospel. The structure of this testimony has made scholars wonder whether Aristocles is Eusebius’ source throughout the passage, or whether Eusebius drew from Aristocles’ work only when he cited specific objections against Cyrenaic epistemology.

The passage is divided into two distinct parts. The first part opens with the observation that the criticisms against the Cyrenaic thesis that the pathē alone are apprehensible are similar to the objections raised against the Pyrrhonians, thus placing them in the broader context of an attack against scepticism in general. This remark is followed by a parenthetical passage concerning the alleged hedonism of Aristippus of Cyrene, the three initial stages of the Cyrenaic succession and the contribution of Aristippus the Younger to the psychological and ethical doctrines of the school. Then the text returns to the epistemology of the Cyrenaics, and in particular to the position of Aristippus the Younger concerning the three conditions of human constitution – pleasure, pain and the neutral condition. Regarding the authorship of this first part, it seems to me that Aristocles is its main source. Eusebius may have changed its original structure somewhat, but I doubt that he altered Aristocles’ views in any significant respect. The parenthetical passage (whose authorship is controversial) may have been introduced by Aristocles in order to give some information about the school, including the psychological positions of Aristippus the Younger which are central to his epistemological views.

The second part of the text is an attack against the epistemological doctrine of the school and its original author is undoubtedly Aristocles. His discussion of Greek scepticism is probably based on Academic texts and it appears likely that both his account and his criticisms of the Cyrenaic doctrine also come from an Academic source.

Aristocles, quoted by Eusebius, Preparation for the Gospel:

So much for those who are believed to follow the philosophy of Pyrrho. The objections raised against the followers of Aristippus the Cyrenean, who claim that only the pathē are apprehensible, are of a similar kind. Aristippus was a companion of Socrates who formulated the Cyrenaic doctrine from which Epicurus took material for his own presentation of the moral end. Aristippus was very voluptuous and pleasure-loving. But he never lectured on the moral end in public. However, he said that the substance of happiness lies potentially in particular pleasures. And by speaking continuously about pleasure, he led his followers to the suspicion that he maintains that living pleasurably is the moral end. One of his disciples was also his daughter, Arete. When she gave birth to a son she named him Aristippus, who was called The Mother-Taught because he was introduced to philosophy by her. He clearly defined the moral end as living pleasantly, introducing the concept of pleasure as motion. He said that there are three conditions regarding our own constitution: one in which we are in pain and which resembles the storm in the sea, another in which we experience pleasure and which is similar to smooth sea-waves (for pleasure is a smooth movement compared to a fair wind); as to the third state, it is an intermediate condition, nearly resembling a calm sea, in which we experience neither pain nor pleasure. Indeed, he said, we have the sensation of these pathē alone. The following objections are raised against these philosophers.

Next would be those who claim that the pathē alone are apprehensible. This claim was made by some of the philosophers from Cyrene. These philosophers maintained that they know absolutely nothing, just as if a very deep sleep weighs down on them, unless somebody standing beside them struck or pricked them; for they said that when they are being burnt or cut, they know that they are undergoing something. But whether the thing which is burning them is fire or that which is cutting them is iron, they cannot tell. But then one would immediately ask those who hold these views whether they know this at least, that they are undergoing and that they are sensing something. If they did not, they would not be able even to say that they know only the pathos; but again, if they do know this, then it is not true that only the pathē are apprehensible, for ‘I am being burnt‘ is a locution, not a pathos. At any rate, it is necessary that at least these three things exist together, the pathos itself, the thing that produced it and the subject undergoing it. Thus, the person apprehending the pathos would certainly sense the affected subject as well. It cannot be that, if one happens to be warmed, one will know that one is being warmed but will not know whether oneself or one’s neighbour is the person who is being warmed. One will also know if this happens now or last year, if it happened in Athens or in Egypt, if one is alive or dead, and further, if one is a human being or a stone. So, one will also know what one is affected by; for people are acquainted with each other and they know the streets, the towns and nourishment. Again, the craftsmen know their own tools, the doctors and the seamen infer by means of signs the things to come, and dogs discover the tracks of the wild animals. Besides, the person who is undergoing a pathos must perceive it either as something welcome or as an unwelcome pathos. Then, by what means will one be able to tell that this is pleasure or this is pain? Or that one is undergoing something, when one is tasting or seeing or hearing? Or that one is tasting something with the tongue, seeing with the eyes or hearing with the ears? And how do they know that they ought to choose this thing but to avoid the other? In fact, if none of these things stirs them, they will have no impulse and no desire. But then they would not be animals either. It follows that they are ridiculous every time that they say that these things have happened to them, but that they do not know how or in what way. In that case, they would not be able to tell even whether they are human beings or whether they are alive. Consequently, neither could they tell whether they say or assert something. At this point, what could one tell such people? Of course, it is surprising if they do not know whether they are on earth or in the heavens. And it would be much more surprising if they do not know whether indeed four is more than three or what one and two make, and yet they affirm that they practise philosophy, for they cannot even say how many fingers they have on their hands or whether each of them is one or many. Thus, they would not know their own name or their fatherland or Aristippus. They would not know whom they love or hate, or what they desire. Nor will they be able to say whether they laughed or wept because one thing was funny and the other sad. So it is obvious that they also do not understand what we are talking about at this very moment. But then such people would not differ at all from peacocks or flies, although even they know the things which are in accordance with nature and the things which are not.

6. Sextus Empiricus:

The Sceptic and empiricist physician Sextus Empiricus (probably second century AD) is our best source on Cyrenaic epistemology. His main references to the doctrine occur in The Outlines of Pyrrhonism and in his work Against the Professors. His reference to the Cyrenaic doctrine is narrowly focused on some fundamental differences between the Pyrrhonian and the Cyrenaic versions of scepticism. On the other hand, his other account contains, arguably, the richest and most subtle presentation of the Cyrenaic position. It occurs in the context of a general survey of the views of the dogmatic philosophers on the subject of the criterion of truth and, more specifically, it is placed towards the middle of the final doxographical session, which is devoted to the doctrines of those dogmatic philosophers who maintained that the criterion lies in enargeia (whether accompanied by logos or not). There are good reasons for believing that the ultimate source of that passage is the work Canonica by Antiochus of Ascalon, a near contemporary of the founder of neo- Pyrrhonism, Aenesidemus (first century BC). Finally, Sextus’ reference to the Cyrenaic doctrine is found in the context of the dogmatic disagreement concerning the existence of sound.

a. Sextus Empiricus, Outlines of Pyrrhonism:

In What Respect Skepticism Differs From Cyrenaic Philosophy:

Some people maintain that the Cyrenaic doctrine is the same as Scepticism, since it too says that only the pathē are apprehensible. In fact, it differs from Scepticism because the former maintains that the moral end is pleasure and the smooth movement of the flesh, whereas we say that it is tranquillity, wherefore it is opposed to their conception of the moral end. Whether pleasure is present or absent, the person who affirms that pleasure is the moral end submits to troubles, as I have concluded in the chapter about it. Besides, we suspend judgement about the external objects, as far as the arguments go. The Cyrenaics, on the other hand, affirm that the external objects have an inapprehensible nature.

b. Sextus Empiricus, Against the Professors:

Now that an account of the Academic doctrine from Plato onwards has been rendered above, it is not perhaps out of place to go over the position of the Cyrenaics. It seems that the school of these men has sprung from the philosophy of Socrates, from which also emerged the succession of Plato’s school. So, the Cyrenaics claim that the pathē are the criteria and that they alone are apprehended and are not deceitful, but that none of the things productive of the pathē is apprehensible or undeceitful. It is possible, they say, to assert infallibly and truly and firmly and incorrigibly that we are being whitened or sweetened, but it is impossible to affirm that the thing productive of the pathos in us is white or sweet, because one may be disposed whitely even by something not-white or may be sweetened by something not-sweet. For just as the sufferer from vertigo or from jaundice is stirred by everything yellowly, and the one suffering from ophthalmia is reddened, and the person who presses down his eye is stirred as if by two objects, and the madman sees Thebes as if it were double and imagines the sun double, and in all these cases it is true that people are undergoing this particular pathos, for instance they are being yellowed or reddened or doubled, but it is considered false that the thing which stirred them is yellow or red or double, likewise it is very plausible for us to assume that one can grasp nothing but one’s own pathē . Hence, we must posit either that the pathē are phainomena or that the things productive of the pathē are phainomena. And if we call the pathē phainomena, we must declare that all phainomena are true and apprehensible. But if we call the things productive of the pathē phainomena, all phainomena are false and inapprehensible. The pathos which occurs in us reveals to us nothing more than itself. Hence, if one must speak but the truth, only the pathos is actually a phainomenon to us; but what is external and productive of the pathos perhaps exists, but it is not a phainomenon to us. And so, we are all unerring with regard to our own pathē, but we all make mistakes with regard to the external object; and those are apprehensible, but this is inapprehensible because the soul is too weak to distinguish it on account of the places, the distances, the motions, the changes, and numerous other causes. Hence they say that no criterion is common to mankind but that common names are assigned to objects. All people in common call something white or sweet, but they do not have something common that is white or sweet. Each person is aware of his own private pathos, but whether this pathos occurs in oneself and in one’s neighbour from a white object one cannot tell oneself, since one is not submitting to the pathos of the neighbour, nor can the neighbour tell, since he is not submitting to the pathos of that other person. And since no pathos is common to us all, it is hasty to declare that what appears to me of a certain kind appears of this same kind to my neighbour as well; for perhaps I am constituted so as to be whitened by the external object when it comes into contact with my senses, while another person has the senses constructed so as to have been disposed differently. In any case, the phainomenon is assuredly not common to us all. And that we really are not all stirred in the same way because of the different constructions of our senses is clear from the cases of people who suffer from jaundice or ophthalmia and from those who are in a normal condition. Just as some persons are affected yellowly, others redly and others whitely from one and the same object, likewise it is also probable that those who are in normal condition are not stirred in the same manner by the same things because of the different construction of their senses, but that the person with grey eyes is stirred in one way, the one with blue eyes in another, and the one with black eyes in another yet different way. It follows that the names which we assign to things are common, but that we have private pathē.

What these philosophers say about the criteria seems to correspond to what they say about the moral ends, for the pathē do also extend to the moral ends. Some of the pathē are pleasant, others are painful and others are inter- mediate; and the painful ones are, they say, evils whose end is pain, the pleasant ones are goods, whose unmistakable end is pleasure, and the intermediates are neither goods nor evils, whose end is neither a good nor an evil, this being a pathos between pleasure and pain. Thus, the pathē are the criteria and the ends of things, and we live, they say, by following these and by attending to evidence and to approval, to evidence regarding the other pathe! and to approval in relation to pleasure.

Such are the teachings of the Cyrenaics, who restricted the criterion more than the school of Plato. The latter considered it a compound of evidence and reason, whereas the Cyrenaics confine it to the enargeiai, i.e., to the pathē alone.

c. Sextus Empiricus, Against the Professors:

From these arguments, it is evident that the whole theory of the musicians about melody consisted essentially in nothing else but the musical notes. So, if these are done away with, music will be nothing. But how could one claim that the musical notes do not exist? Because, we will answer, they belong to the genus of sound and because it has been proven in the memoirs of Scepticism that sound does not exist, by appealing to the evidence of the Dogmatists. And besides, the Cyrenaic philosophers claim that only the pathe! exist, and nothing else. So, since sound is not a pathos but rather something capable of producing a pathos, it is not one of the things that exist. To be sure, by denying the existence of every sensory object, the schools of Democritus and of Plato deny the existence of sound as well, since sound is taken to be a sensory object.

d. Sextus Empiricus, Against the Professors:

According to some people the Cyrenaics too endorsed the ethical branch of philosophy only, and dismissed the physical and logical branches as contribu- ting nothing to a happy life. However, some have thought that they (sc. the Cyrenaics) refute themselves from the way they divide ethics into headings – one dealing with objects of choice and avoidance, another with the pathē , yet another with actions, another with causes, and finally one with arguments. Among these, they say, the heading dealing with causes in fact is drawn from physics, while that dealing with arguments is drawn from logic.

 7. Diogenes Laërtius:

Diogenes Laertius’ work Lives of Eminent Philosophers may have been written in the third century AD. The Cyrenaic school is discussed in book  of that work, which also contains the Lives of Socrates and of several Socratic philosophers in addition to the Cyrenaics. The structure of the testimony on the Cyrenaics comprises the Life of Aristippus of Cyrene, followed by a passage on the successions of the Cyrenaic school, and then by the successive presentation of the doctrines of the Cyrenaics proper, i.e. ‘those who remained attached to the sect of Aristippus and were known as Cyrenaics’, of Hegesias and his disciples, Anniceris and his disciples, and the sect of Theodorus.

The account focuses on the ethical doctrines of the Cyrenaics, but parts of it are crucial for the interpretation of the epistemology of the school. It supplies information about the physiological features of the doctrine and it cites two tenets directly relevant to Cyrenaic epistemology. The first occurs at the end of Aristippus’ Life and concerns his definition of the moral end as ‘the smooth motion resulting in sensation’. The second tenet is encountered towards the end of the section on the Cyrenaics proper: the pathē themselves are apprehensible, but not the things that cause them. Although this is the central epistemological position of the Cyrenaics, it is not further analysed in this context. It may be mentioned in order to support the claim that the Cyrenaics held that things appear incomprehensible and for that reason abandoned the study of physics.

Diogenes Laertius, Lives of Eminent Philosophers:

He (sc. Aristippus of Cyrene) declared that the moral end is the smooth motion when it comes forth to consciousness.

(86) The philosophers who abode by the teaching of Aristippus and were called Cyrenaics had the following beliefs. There are two pathē, pain and pleasure, pleasure being a smooth motion and pain a rough motion. (87) One pleasure does not differ from another nor is one pleasure more pleasant than another in any respect. And pleasure is agreeable while pain is repulsive to all animals. However, notably according to Panaetius in his work On the Philosophical Sects, the bodily pleasure, which is the moral end, is not the static pleasure occurring after the removal of pain or, as it were, the freedom from discomfort, which Epicurus accepts and maintains to be the moral end.

(88) Individual pleasure is desirable for its own sake, whereas happiness is not desirable for its own sake but for the sake of individual pleasures. That pleasure is the moral end is proved by the fact that, from an early age onwards, we welcome it without making a deliberate choice, and once we obtain it, we seek for nothing more and avoid nothing so much as its opposite, pain. Pleasure is good even if it comes from the most unseemly actions, as Hippobotus says in his book On the Philosophical Sects. Even if the action is inappropriate, still the pleasure that results from it is desirable for its own sake and is good. (89) However, the removal of pain, as it is defined by Epicurus, seems to them (sc. the Cyrenaics proper) not to be pleasure at all, nor the absence of pleasure pain; for they hold that both pleasure and pain are in motion, whereas the absence of pain or the absence of pleasure is not a motion, since the absence of pain resembles the condition of somebody who is asleep. They assert that some people may fail to choose pleasure because of some perversion. Not all psychic pleasures and pains are ultimately dependent on bodily pleasures and pains. We are disinterestedly delighted at the prosperity of our country as if it were our own prosperity. Again, they do not accept that pleasure consists in the memory of past goods or in the expectation of goods to come, as Epicurus held, (91) for the motion of the soul expires with time.

They (sc. the Cyrenaics proper) said that the pathē are apprehensible themselves, not the things from which they derive. And they abandoned the study of nature because of its manifest uncertainty; but they engaged in logic because of its usefulness. However, Meleager in the second book of his work On Philosophical Doctrines and Clitomachus in the first book of his work On the Philosophical Sects attest that the Cyrenaics considered both physics and dialectic useless.

They (sc. the Cyrenaics proper) maintain that the sorrow of one person exceeds that of another, and that the senses do not always tell the truth.

They (sc. the Hegesians) also believed that there is nothing pleasant or unpleasant by nature. It is because of the lack of something or its rarity or its superabundance that some people feel pleasure while others feel disgust. Poverty and wealth have nothing to do with pleasure, for the rich and the poor do not feel pleasure in different ways. Slavery and freedom, noble birth or low birth, glory or dishonour, are also indifferent in measuring pleasure.

They (sc. the Hegesians) refuted the senses, since they do not yield accurate knowledge. And they claimed to do whatever appeared reasonable. They also said that errors should be forgiven, for no person errs voluntarily, but because he is compelled by a pathos. And we must not hate the erring man, but we should teach him better. The wise man does not have so much privilege over other people in his choice of goods as he has in avoiding evils, positing as a goal to live without bodily or mental pain. (96) This is the advantage gained by those who have been indifferent about the things capable of producing pleasure.

The Annicerians agreed in other respects with them (sc. the Hegesians, but also the Cyrenaics proper); but they admitted that friendship and gratitude and respect for parents exist in life, and that the wise man will act in some cases for the sake of his country.

He (sc. Theodorus) said that the world was his country. Theft, adultery and sacrilege are allowed upon occasion; for none of these things is wrong by nature, once we remove the belief which is kept up in order to bind together the multitude.

The latest testimonies, only recently included in the evidence about Cyrenaic epistemology, come from two Christian authors, well-versed in Greek and Roman culture: Eusebius of Caesarea (who appears to speak on his own account in this passage) and the fourth–fifth century AD. Latin author and Church Father, St Augustine.

8. Eusebius:

Eusebius cites the central epistemological thesis of the Cyrenaics in the same breath as the attitudes of the Pyrrhonians and the positions of Metrodorus and Protagoras, thus suggesting that their theory has affinities with scepticism, sensationalism and relativism.

a. Eusebius, Preparation for the Gospel:

Aside from the philosophers that have been set forth by us, in this gymnastic contest the stadium will also contain, stripped of all truth, those from the opposite side who took up arms against all the dogmatic philosophers put together (I mean the school of Pyrrho), and who declared that nothing amongst men is apprehensible, and also the school of Aristippus, who maintain that only the pathē are apprehensible, and again the schools of Metrodorus and Protag- oras who hold that we must trust only the sensations of the body.

b. Eusebius, Preparation for the Gospel:

After him (sc. Socrates) the school of Aristippus of Cyrene and then later the school of Aristo of Chios tried to claim that in doing philosophy we should study only ethics; for it is both possible and useful. In complete contrast, accounts of nature are neither apprehensible nor, even if it turns out that they are clearly understood, do they have any usefulness.

9. St. Augustine:

St Augustine’s testimony is crucial to our discussion. In the treatise Contra Academicos, he sets out to examine a hypothetical challenge that a sceptic might address to a person, namely that one is deceived in believing that one is tasting something sweet while, in fact, one is dreaming. In his retort, St Augustine emphasises the irrefutability of subjective experience and mentions in that connection the doctrines of the Epicureans and of the Cyrenaics. The importance of this passage lies in the fact that it might be considered to raise the problem of the external world, and it also might appear to support Plutarch’s claim that the Cyrenaics and the Epicureans held very similar positions regarding the reliability of the senses.

St Augustine, Contra Academicos:

This I say, that a person, when he is tasting something, can swear with good faith that he knows through his own palate that this is sweet, or to the contrary, and he cannot be brought away from that knowledge by any Greek trickery. Who would be so shameless as to say to me when I am licking something with delight: ‘maybe you are not tasting, but this is a dream’? Do I resist? But that would delight me even if I were asleep. And so, no likeness of false things confuses that which I said I know, and an Epicurean or the Cyrenaics may perhaps say many other things in favour of the senses, against which I have observed that nothing was said by the Academics.

Source:

Tsouna, V. (1998). The Epistemology of the Cyrenaic School. Cambridge University Press.

Theodor Gomperz - Greek Thinkers: A History of Ancient Philosophy - “Cyrenaic Epistemology’

Below is a selection of Theodor Gomperz’s A History of Ancient Philosophy detailing the philosophy of Aristippus and the Cyrenaics as regards their epistemic theories. I have underlined important material for emphasis. 

Cyrenaic Epistemology:

In the theory of knowledge, the analytic intellect of the Cyrenaics penetrated to still greater depths than in ethics. We cannot take account of their work in this field without making the reader to some extent a partner in our investigation. The regrettable loss of all the works of this school, the meagreness and the one-sidedness of the notices relating to them, almost all of which are of a polemical character, compel us to linger for some time over the subject, and to give it a detailed consideration, the length of which will, we hope, be rewarded by its fruits. 

The Cyrenaic theory of knowledge was compressed into a formula which occurs in the same form in different and independent accounts, and therefore must certainly have been taken from the original documents. It runs as follows : “Our modes of being affected are alone knowable.” For the explanation of this proposition, our authorities appeal to the most diverse instances of sense-perception. They allege in the spirit, partly perhaps in the very words, of the Cyrenaics that we do not know that honey is sweet, that chalk is white, that fire burns, or that the knife-blade cuts: all that we can report is our own states of feeling; we have a sensation of sweetness, we feel ourselves burnt or cut, and so on. The first impression received by the attentive reader of this book may possibly be that in these utterances we are again confronted by the Leucippic-Democritean doctrine touching the subjective nature of most sensations (“According to convention, there are a sweet and a bitter, a hot and a cold,” and so on. Cf. Vol. I. p. 320). But this impression will not bear examination. For there is no repetition of what formed the counterpart of that declaration concerning the subjective or secondary properties of things, namely, a proclamation of atoms and the void as strictly objective realities. Not only so, but nothing else is introduced as a strictly objective existence to take the place of atoms and the void. We must consider, too, that our records, inadequate as they are, present us, in their central features at any rate, with the testimony of competent and well- informed students of the earlier philosophers ; and these would not have omitted to mention the identity or approximate identity of two doctrines. Still, the present is not an unsuitable occasion to allude to the theory of Leucippus, if only as the starting-point, and almost indispensable premiss of the theory now engaging our attention. In the latter we have, without any doubt, a continuation and expansion of the earlier attempt, related to it as the theories of Berkeley or Hume are to those of Hobbes or Locke. 

Expositions in some detail of this theory of knowledge occur in three different quarters. There are two late philosophical authors, namely, the empiric physician, Sextus (about 200 A.D.), and a Peripatetic, or adherent of the Aristotelian school, named Aristocles, who came about a generation earlier, and of whom the ecclesiastical historian Eusebius has preserved considerable fragments in his “Praeparatio Evangelica.” Lastly there is Plato. This reversal of the natural order in which the profound philosopher, the contemporary of Aristippus, is made to yield precedence to late authors who were immeasurably inferior to him in every respect, is based upon the following reason. Those two later authorities treat expressly and deliberately of Aristippus and his school ; Plato gives us, in a section of the “Theaetetus,” what purports to be a secret doctrine of the sophist Protagoras, but really belongs, as we believe, along with Friedrich Schleiermacher and several others, to Aristippus. This conjecture for conjecture it is, though anything but a random or reckless one rests entirely on the agreement between Plato's exposition and the above-mentioned accounts, which, nevertheless, are thereby supplemented to a not inconsiderable degree, and, so to speak, illuminated from within. 

Aristocles, in truth, gives us little more than the formula quoted above, to which he subjoins a lengthy polemic, betraying his total inability to appreciate his opponent's standpoint. Sextus is an adherent and advocate of sceptic principles. As such he is at pains, as we have already remarked a propos of Democritus (Vol. I. p. 359), to make the representatives of other schools into allies of scepticism. It is thus not surprising that he clothes his account of the Cyrenaic theory of knowledge in the language of his own school, and that he gives the sceptical or negative side of that theory the predominance. But that which more particularly moves our astonishment in this short account of the scepticism of the Cyrenaics, as in the parallel account given by Plutarch, is the lavish use of words expressing dogmatic assurance, such as “true,” “incontrovertible,” “unshakable,” “infallible,” “reliable,” “sound.” How is this contradiction to be explained? For this purpose it seems necessary to penetrate more deeply into the mind of these philosophers and the guiding principles of their thought. What at first may here seem hypothetical, will, we hope, gradually improve its claim to be fact in the course of the investigation. 

The distinction between primary and secondary qualities, the great achievement, rich in consequences, of Leucippus, had drawn the attention of thinkers to the subjective element in sense-perception generally. This exaltation of the subject, this insistence on his cardinal significance for the genesis of sensation, natural and obvious as it seems, was a comparatively late development ; when, however, it had once appeared, its influence on the mind of inquirers could not but gain in strength as it became more and more familiar to them. The question was bound to be raised whether those perceptions to which absolutely objective validity was still conceded, were in reality fully entitled to the distinction. For example, the perception of colour was held to be subjectively conditioned, but not that of forms. This violent separation of what was so closely related could not be maintained intact when once attention had been drawn to a number of illusions to which the eye is subject even outside the field of colour-perception. New difficulties were raised by the staff which appears broken when dipped in water, by the different apparent magnitudes of one and the same object as viewed by the two eyes, by the double vision which may be the result either of a pathological condition or of sideward pressure upon one eye. The sense of touch itself, which passed for the type of true objectivity, was found, on closer observation, to labour under grave deficiencies. Thus the fact that, when two fingers are crossed, a single pellet may be felt as two, supplied much matter for thought. (A few, but not all, of these illusions are mentioned in the account given by Sextus; others are referred to in the section of Aristotle's Metaphysics which deals with the relativistic schools of thought.) Some, no doubt, were satisfied with the reflexion that the message of the one sense, or of the one organ, may be corrected by that of another, just as the normal condition corrects the testimony of the abnormal one. But what guarantee have we so might the doubters answer that equally grave deceptions do not occur in other cases, where no correction is attainable ? And, apart from that, had not Democritus already pointed out that it is not the number, not the majority or minority, whether of persons or of conditions, that can decide between truth and false- hood (cf. Vol. I. p. 360) ? Here we call to mind the violent attacks of the Eleatics on the testimony of the senses in general. This tendency of thought to be hostile to sense was necessarily reinforced by the growth of reflexion, and especially by the placing of such observations as we have just mentioned in the forefront of discussion. Nor was Eleaticism by any means dead; it lived on in the school of those Socratics whose home was at Megara, and whom we took leave to call “Neo-Eleatics,” as being the heirs of Zeno and his predecessors. There can be no doubt that the old cry, “The senses are liars; do not believe them ! Truth dwells outside and above the world of sense,” was now raised more loudly than before. It woke the strongest echo in the mind of Plato. But the opponents of the Eleatics, Protagoras for example, had successors as well, and we ask with what weapons could the old conflict be continued? The proposition, “All that is perceived is real” had from the first a subjective tinge, which appears in the reference to “man” as the “measure of all things” but which finds its clearest expression in the treatise “On the Art.” This sophist's discourse, filled with the spirit of Protagoras, contains a passage which runs as follows: “If the Non-Existent can be seen like the Existent, I do not understand how any one can call it non-existent, when the eyes can see it and the mind recognize it as existent” (cf. Vol. I. p. 454). That which in an earlier generation had been a casual glimpse, a fleeting inspiration, now became the central stronghold for the defence of the witness of the senses. Its champions abandon, so to speak, their advanced posts and outworks to the enemy, and retire to the inmost parts of the fortress, the sensations themselves. These are no longer held as the pledges and guarantees of something external; while the adversary receives the most sweeping concessions, his most effective weapon of attack is wrested from his hands. However freely we admit that sensation can bring no valid testimony to the nature, or even the existence, of 'external objects, the sensation itself remains undeniable; it possesses unconditional validity or truth in itself, and, in combination with the other processes of consciousness, makes up a sum of knowledge which is perfectly adequate for all human purposes. 

He who encounters for the first time this renunciation of belief in an external world may be excused if he imagines himself in a madhouse. “If you believe in the truth of this doctrine of yours” it was in such terms as these that Bishop Berkeley and his adherents were apostrophized “you may just as well run your head against a lamp-post, for the non-existent post cannot possibly hurt your equally non-existent head.” To which the reply was regularly returned, “We do not deny the sensation of resistance, nor any of the other sensations of which is composed the image or idea of a post, of a head, and of the whole external world ; that which we deny, or that, at least, of which we know nothing “as one section of the school affirms” is that mysterious something assumed by you to lie behind those phenomena which are present to our as to every other similar consciousness, and which are bound together by unalterable laws of sequence and coexistence.” What “we call the idea of a tree, the idea of a stone, the idea of a horse, the idea of a man” so we are told by a modern advocate of this school of thought, the older Mill, in his “Analysis of the Phenomena of the Human Mind” are the ideas of a certain number of sensations, received together so frequently that they coalesce as it were, and are spoken of under the idea of “unity.” Similarly, we read in Plato's “Theatetus: “To such a group [of sensations] is assigned the name of man, of stone, of beast, and of every other thing.” Plato is here dealing with thinkers on whose subtlety he lays particular emphasis, whom he places in the sharpest contrast with the materialists, who believe in nothing but what they can grasp in their hands. He says of them, further, that they resolve everything into processes and events, completely banishing the concept of Being. He represents them, by the aid of that transparent fiction of a secret doctrine of Protagoras, as the successors of the great sophist; and, lastly, he describes for us a theory of sensation which is peculiar to them, one to which we shall presently have to pay some attention. The reader will probably be satisfied that the only contemporaries of Plato to whom this picture could apply were those who maintained that “modes of being affected are alone knowable,” that the “external thing” supposed to underlie a group of such modes was “possibly existent,” but, in any case, “inaccessible to us” (Sextus). Again, we must express regret for the scantiness of our information. We do not know how these earliest representatives of the school of thought now called phenomenalistic, settled accounts with traditional views. Did they undertake to explain the origin of the latter? Did they, like an English psychologist and a German-Austrian physicist of our own day, point to the psychical processes in virtue of which an aggregate of possibilities of sensation “appears to acquire a permanent existence which our sensations themselves do not possess, and consequently a greater reality than belongs to our sensations”? Or did they appeal to the fact that “the colours, sounds, odours of bodies are fleeting,” while the “tangible,” exempt in the main from temporal and individual change, remains as a “persistent kernel,” appearing as the background, substratum, or “vehicle of the fleeting qualities attached to it,” and retained as such, by force of mental habit, even when “the conviction has gained ground, that sight, hearing, and touch are intimately related to each other?” or lastly, did they contemplate the possibility that the conception of material substance arises from the confluence of those two streams of thought? These are questions which we cannot answer. But we should not be in the least surprised to learn that they never advanced beyond the rudiments of the problem, although they can hardly have neglected all criticism of the concept of Being. 

The account which Plato gives of their theory of sensation must also be taken as authentic only in essentials. Many a detail in the picture may well be due to that creative intellect which was hardly ever satisfied with the bare reproduction of other men's opinions. For this reason we shall only advert to the main features of that theory. According to it, two elements, an active and a passive, come into play in the production of every sensation. This co-operation is designated as movement, and connected, in jest or earnest, with the Heraclitean doctrine of perpetual flux. From the meeting of two such elements, which only by meeting acquire their characters of active and passive, sensation and the object of sensation take their rise simultaneously colours along with visual sensations, sounds along with auditory sensations, and so forth. It is denied that a previously existing hard, soft, warm, cold, or white thing is perceived ; all this enters upon existence simultaneously with the perception. But how are we to conceive of this process which creates, at one and the same time, the subjective sensation and the objective quality, if not the object possessing the quality ? Plato, as we have remarked, terms the process movement, and clearly attributes to it a spatial character. What we have called the elements concerned in the movement, Plato leaves somewhat indefinite, and the consequence is a certain regrettable want of clearness, which may or may not have been intended. In the reasoning on which the doctrine is founded there is no mention of the material or corporeal; the emphatically repeated denial of all absolute existence, the “activities, processess, and all the invisible,” which are placed in such strong contrast with tangible things, lead us far away from the material world. Or rather, they would take us entirely out of it, were it not for the fact that the substitutes for the strict concept of matter which were used by many ancient thinkers, Plato and Aristotle among them, laboured under a remarkable degree of haziness. Thus the possibility is not entirely excluded that, in the original exposition at least, some species of matter, devoid of form and qualities, was designated as the subject of that movement. But we must not lose sight of yet another possibility, namely, that Aristippus himself may have had in view a purely material process. This last and more natural supposition gave rise to the reproach, urged against the Cyrenaics, of moving in a circle, by resolving the corporeal into sensations, and then deducing sensation from the corporeal. The justice of this reproach is to say the least, doubtful. For in no case can it be contended that the phenomenalist, merely as such, is debarred from studying the physiology of the senses or natural science in general. He will, of course, begin by declaring that bodies or material substances are for him nothing but complexes of permanent possibilities of sensation, or else similar abstractions resting in the last resort on sensations. But he is none the less at liberty to treat of the bodily conditions of each special sensation, and of the material conditions of any other process he may choose to consider. It is possible to contest the admissibility of his analysis, but not the legitimacy of this application of it. The procedure of the Cyrenaics may quite possibly have resembled that which we have just described. This would accord with the circumstance that they were accused of having reintroduced into their system at a later stage the physics and logic which they began by banishing from it. For the crown of their doctrinal edifice (its fourth and fifth parts) is stated to have been concerned with “causes” (physics), and “grounds of proof” (logic). 

What more especially was the character of this logic of theirs, is a question to which we should be glad to be able to give an answer. There is an entire lack of positive statements on the subject. Yet it might have been conjectured a priori that in ancient times, as in modern, a phenomenalistic theory of knowledge and a hedonistic-utilitarian system of ethics were accompanied by an empirical and inductive tendency in logic. That such a logic did exist in the schools of the later Epicureans, we learnt, more than thirty years ago, from a work of Philodemus, which had lain concealed by the ashes of Herculaneum. When we first attempted the reconstruction of that mutilated treatise, we were able to point to traces, hitherto unobserved, of similar doctrines in the schools of the Sceptics and of the Empiric physicians. What was the common root? Light has been thrown on this question by Ernst Laas, who drew attention to a pregnant reference to this subject, which had previously been overlooked, in Plato's “Republic.” This passage deals with the preservation in the memory of past events, with the careful consideration of what happened first, what afterwards, what at the same time, and with the deduction, from such sources, of the safest possible forecast of the future. The language employed, for all its picturesqueness, strongly reminds us of the expressions used by more recent authors well acquainted with the inductive logic of later antiquity. We shall hardly go wrong if we connect this passage, not, as was done by another investigator, with Protagoras, but with Plato's contemporary, Aristippus. The conclusion which we draw from all our data taken together is that Aristippus laid the foundations for a system of logic which should be nothing else than a body of rules for ascertaining the sequences and the coexistences of phenomena. The Cyrenaic was, no doubt, prepared for weighty objections against his views, and such were probably raised in abundance by his contentious and inquisitive opponents. “You do not believe in the reality of external things” so may his critics well have exclaimed “at least you deny that they can be known; where, then, do you leave room, we do not say for science, but the most elementary foresight? What is the foundation of the commonest empirical truths which no one denies, not even yourself? How can you infer to-morrow from to-day? Whence do you learn that fire burns, that water quenches thirst, that men are mortal, that there is any permanence in those connexions and co-ordinations on which the whole conduct of life depends, as well as the special methods and processes of the artist, the mechanic, the physician, the pilot, the farmer, and the rest? We shall not be guilty of any great recklessness in conjecture if we assume that the Cyrenaics felt themselves compelled to return some answer to these questions, and not admit, if only by silence, that in renouncing all cognizable objects they also renounced all knowledge and all regulation of conduct in accordance with knowledge. And the very answer which their epistemological assumptions allowed them to give is contained in that allusion of Plato to which we have referred. There is in that passage no mention of objects, but only of events and happenings; and similarly it is quite possible that the inductive logic alluded to above may have grown out of a mode of apprehending the world which neither sought nor found behind things or existences anything else than complexes of phenomena, bound together by fixed laws. There is thus something more than a small probability that the earliest emergence of a radical criticism of knowledge was accompanied by the first formulation of that canon of knowledge which not only can be associated with such criticism, but has once more been so associated in our own century, that is to say, the rules governing the ascertainment of purely phenomenal successions and coexistences. 

But it is time to return from this digression, to leave the Cyrenaic treatment of the chief problem of knowledge, known to us as it is only in its main features, for a subject on which all doubt may be said to be excluded the Cyrenaic doctrine of sensation, borrowed by them from Protagoras, but certainly further elaborated by Aristippus. That, properly speaking, there are no illusions of the senses, that, on the contrary, every sensation is the natural and necessary result of the factors which produce it, is a highly important truth which Plato, in the “Theaetetus,” proclaims with all the clearness that can be desired, in close connexion with undoubted Cyrenaic doctrines. It is not the majority or the minority of the subjects who feel in this or that manner, it is not the regularly predominating or the causally occurring state of the individual percipient that can establish a fundamental distinction between sensations; although, as we may add, the conclusions which we draw from the two classes of sensation may be of very different values for the ordering of life. That the authors of this theory were far in advance of their century is clear from the fact that some of the most eminent of our own contemporaries have not thought it superfluous to proclaim and insist upon those same truths. In 1867 Hermann Helmholtz wrote as follows: 

“A red-blind person sees cinnabar as black or as a dark- yellowish grey, and that is the proper reaction for his peculiarly constituted eye. He only needs to know that his eye is different from those of other men. In itself, the one sensation is no truer and no falser than the other ['My sensation is true for me,' as we read in the Theatetus], even though those who see red have the great majority on their side. The red colour of cinnabar only exists at all in so far as there are eyes made like those of the majority of mankind. Cinnabar has exactly the same title to the property of being black, that is, to the red-blind.”

And again: “A sweet thing which is sweet for no one is an absurdity.” In the following year another philosophical physicist, to whom we have already alluded, explained his views on the same question in these words 

The expression, sense-illusion proves that we are not yet fully conscious, or at least have not yet deemed it necessary to incorporate the fact into our ordinary language, that the senses represent things neither wrongly nor correctly. All that can be truly said of the sense-organs is that wider different circumstances they produce different sensations and perceptions. . . . And it is usual to call the unusual effects deceptions, or illusions.”

We have still to consider a negative circumstance of some importance. The problems of change, of inherence, of predication, which played so great a part in the investigations of the Megarians, the Cynics, and even of Plato, are entirely absent from all reports of the teaching of the Cyrenaics. Nor should we be surprised at this, for all these riddles are offshoots of the concept of Being, which the authors of the theory of sensation expounded in the “Theatetus” endeavoured, as Plato expressly informs us, to abolish altogether. The desire to be rid of the difficulties which attend this concept was, we may be sure, a considerable factor in the thought of the earlier as of the later phenomenalists. There is an entire lack of evidence to show how far their criticism of the concept of Being took a polemical turn, directed against members of other Socratic schools. It is possible that this very subject had its part in the controversies which raged between Aristippus and Antisthenes, and again between Theodorus, a late member of the African school, and Stilpo the Megarian.

Philodemus of Gadara references Aristippus of Cyrene

The Epicurean philosopher Philodemus of Gadara offers a rare explicit reference to Aristippus of Cyrene in a fragmentary segment from his wo...